Ethical justification of a randomized clinical trial requires at the o
utset that the investigators be able to state an honest null hypothesi
s regarding the therapies to be compared. For example, in a randomized
clinical trial with only two arms (A and B), it is necessary to state
that there is no scientifically validated reason to predict that ther
apy A will prove to be either superior or inferior to therapy B. Moreo
ver, there must be no therapy C known to be superior to A and B unless
there is a cogent reason to reject therapy C; the population of resea
rch subjects will consist either of those in whom therapy C has been t
ried without success or individuals who are aware of therapy C and hav
e rejected it for various reasons. Thus, theoretically, the patients e
nrolled in a randomized clinical trial are assured that they will rece
ive one of the two best known therapies for their condition. At first
glance, one might conclude that randomized clinical trials do, in gene
ral, help the patient. There are some features of at least some clinic
al trials, however, that may be detrimental to the interests of some p
atients. It commonly is said, for example, that patients in randomized
clinical trials are deprived of the ''good of personal care.''1 The p
hysician-investigator may be constrained by rigid protocol requirement
s from being responsive to the particular needs and desires of the pat
ient. Additionally, the process of obtaining informed consent to rando
mized clinical trials may be preemptive: patients who might have chose
n palliative care rather than chemotherapy may not be afforded adequat
e opportunity to make such a choice. Any randomized clinical trial sho
uld maximize the likelihood of helping the patient.