Over the past five years prominority gerrymanders have given the Supre
me Court fits. three Justices appear to be of the opinion that any con
sideration of race in crafting voting districts is unconstitutional. F
our stand ready generally to uphold such districts essentially on the
ground that they are ordinary (perhaps even unusually benign) instance
s of affirmative action. The two in the middle, however, quite consist
ently vote to invalidate such districts, though they allow that they a
re sometimes permissible, but seem to be having trouble getting togeth
er on a theory that tells, when and why. The dominant purpose test of
Miller v. Johnson-which, so far as one can tell, officially represents
the law as of 1998-proves ultimately incoherent, while its predecesso
r and sometime stand-in, Shaw v. Reno's bizarre shape test, is widely
held to lack connection with articulable constitutional values. Profes
sor fly argues that of the two, Shaw v. Reno's test is preferable not
only because of its relative intelligibility, but also because, at lea
st under current conditions, it puts in place a political safeguard, e
ncouraging state legislatures themselves to moderate both racial and,
what he regards as even more clearly constitutionally offensive, polit
ical gerrymandering. He goes on to argue, however, that those conditio
ns are unlikely to prevail for very long, thus-complete judicial abste
ntion being indefensible in this concert-making it incumbent upon the
Court to face head-on the ultimate issues of principle at stake here:
whether it is constitutional to any degree to take race or political p
arty into account in shaping voting districts. He closes by suggesting
that it is not, and briefly exploring what options capable of avoidin
g the severe reduction of minority representation such a holding would
leave the political branches.